Kelsen: Formalism, Efficacy, and Acceptability
For my dear
advisees, especially for Vitor Marcellino and Pollyane Leitão
Kelsen
establishes three requisites for a legal norm to be said to be valid. The first
one is its belonging to an existing legal system, that is its legality. The
second one is its containing of a sanction or connection to other norm which contains
a sanction, that is its coercion. The third one is its being obeyed, that is
its efficacy. Kelsen also states that his pure theory of law is formal, which means that it admits of any content to be law and its requisites
are completely void of content.
In the case
of the third requisite for the validity of legal norms, that is efficacy, we
can challenge Kelsen’s belief that such requisite is indeed formal by reasoning
as follows: a) if a requisite is to be formal, it must make no distinction
among different possible contents; b) if the requisite of efficacy is to be
formal, then efficacy must make no distinction among different possible
contents of norms; c) if efficacy is to make no distinction among different possible
contents of norms, then norms with every possible content must be able to be
efficacious. But c) is not only an empirical statement (therefore, not much of
a candidate for being formal), but it is also a glaringly false one.
Therefore, efficacy is not a formal requisite.
We can go
one step further and connect the issue of efficacy with that one of acceptability.
It is obviously true that one of the many possible reasons for a norm to be
inefficacious is the addressees’ rejection of its content, that is its lack of
acceptability. If at least in some cases of inefficacy, the norm is inefficacious
due to its unacceptability, then at least in some cases inefficacy will be an
issue that depends on the content of the norm. Well, an issue depending on the
content of the norm cannot, by definition, be a formal one. Therefore, efficacy
is not a formal requisite.
This
challenge could be met with the following response: If the efficacy of the norm
were in any measure depending on the acceptance of its content, then it would
not be a formal requisite. But in Kelsen’s theory, the efficacy of a norm is
obtained by means of the sanction. Kelsen denies that a sanction alone can
bring about efficacy for a norm of behavior, but, even when it does not, it
creates a second kind of efficacy for a norm, that is the efficacy of its
sanction. Then, even when the content of a norm of behavior were so unacceptable
as to turn that norm inefficacious in the first sense (people not acting
according to the norm commandment), the application of its sanction to the disobeying
addressee would still turn it efficacious in that second sense (people who do
not act according to the norm commandment being sanctioned).
However, it
would only postpone the problem. The sanction would only be a solution for the
problem of inefficacy if the sanction itself could never be inefficacious. But
sanctions also have contents, and their contents can also be unacceptable. If
at least in some cases the unacceptability of a norm entails its inefficacy,
then at least in some cases sanctions that are unacceptable would also be
inefficacious. It would happen not only in cases where sanctions are inhumane or
disproportional, but also in cases where the sanction punishes the disobedience
to an unacceptable norm of behavior. If the behavior commanded by the norm is
unacceptable, then a sanction punishing the disobedience to such norm would also
be unacceptable. If in some cases unacceptable norms of behavior can become
inefficacious, then the unacceptable sanctions punishing those who disobey such
norms cannot wait for a better fate. Otherwise we would be counting on totally cold-hearted
sanction enforcers, capable of applying any sanction no matter how unacceptable
it is, but, if we could appeal to fictional beings like that, we would have no
reason not to appeal instead to perfectly obedient addressees, capable of
obeying norms of behavior no matter how unacceptable they are. Fictions could
have solved our problems many steps earlier. If, however, we are not fictionalizing,
then the assumption that all sanction enforcers are totally cold-hearted is, to
say the least, very unlikely to be true. Thus, sanctions would also depend on
their efficacy, which would also in at least some cases depend on their content; therefore, efficacy,
with or without sanction, would keep not being a formal requisite.
If that is
right, we can not only come to the conclusion that efficacy cannot be a formal
requisite, but we can invert that conclusion against Kelsen’s purposes and say
that, introducing efficacy as a requisite for validity, Kelsen sheltered a
material wolf covert with sheep’s formal clothing. For saying that every
content can be valid law, but, in order to be valid law, that content must be
efficacious is tantamount to saying that, as not every content can be
efficacious, not every content can be valid law. And any theory that recognizes
that is not a formalistic theory anymore.
Comentários
Parabéns pela publicação e pelos questionamentos que o sr mesmo já levantou no outro post.
Sobre a questão dos critérios de validade, gostaria de levantar uma questão. O sr aponta que são 3 os critérios de validade para Kelsen: legalidade, coerção e eficácia. Quanto a coerção, creio que este não é especificamente um critério de validade para Kelsen, e sim um critério para dizer se a norma é ou não jurídica, ou seja, ligado ao próprio conceito de direito. Assim, parecem ser coisas intrinsecamente relacionadas, porém distintas, visto que podemos falar em normas ditas jurídicas, mas que carecem de validade. Creio que, para kelsen, a falta de um ato de coerção ligado a uma determinada norma exclui a sua "juridicidade" (se assim podemos dizer), não diretamente sua validade.
Abraços